header logo

Wittgenstein: Comprehending the Philosophy and Language Theory

Wittgenstein: Comprehending the Philosophy and Language Theory


“The limits of my language mean the limits of my world.” 

the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein 


“Those who know nothing of foreign languages know nothing of their own.” ― Johann Wolfgang von Goethe


Oveview:


Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus has a core ethical message, revealing that philosophical problems often yield minimal solutions.


The Tractatus comprises seven sets of numbered propositions, concluding with the enigmatic statement, "What we cannot speak about we must pass over in silence."


Essential propositions in the Tractatus delve into the fundamental concept of the world, propositions as representations of reality, and the role of logical constants in describing facts.


Wittgenstein asserts that "What can be shown, cannot be said," emphasizing that the essence of the world is best expressed as "This is how things are."


While Wittgenstein's philosophy hints at an "accept and endure" ethics, he explicitly deems the Tractatus' propositions as meaningless, challenging their profoundness.


The "picture theory" of meaning, which suggests that meaningful propositions depict empirical facts, has had a notable impact on interpretations of the Tractatus but encounters internal problems.


Wittgenstein's primary objective in the Tractatus is to demonstrate that many philosophical questions are inherently nonsensical or non-problems. He advocates clarifying language's logic to dispel confusion rather than constructing elaborate philosophical theories.


Wittgenstein: Unlocking the Limits of Language 


Understanding Wittgenstein's Work


Leading philosopher of the 20th century Ludwig Wittgenstein is well known for his in-depth investigation of language and its constraints. Throughout his career, Wittgenstein's philosophy changed, leading to the publication of two important works: the early "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus" and the later "Philosophical Investigations."


Early Wittgenstein: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus


Wittgenstein offered a novel viewpoint in his "Tractatus," emphasizing the function of language's fundamental structure in describing the outside world. This early work, which focused on the following important issues, set the groundwork for comprehending the nature of language and philosophy.


Foundation of the Tractatus: 

The German version of Wittgenstein's "Tractatus" was released in 1921, and an English translation followed. It was impacted by Schopenhauer's philosophical theories as well as his previous works.



Limitations of Language: 

According to Wittgenstein, "what can be said at all can be said clearly, and what we cannot talk about we must pass over in silence." His investigation into the limitations of language began with this claim.


World as Representation: 

According to Wittgenstein, propositions and thoughts both have the same logical structure and are representations of the outside world. The core of his thinking is this notion.


The Picture Theory: 

His "picture theory of language," which holds that ideas and propositions are like pictures that match the logical structure of a situation, was first proposed by him. The idea that language should reflect the logical structure of reality was emphasized by this point of view.



Limits of Language: 

Because of Wittgenstein's view of language, meaningful propositions that follow logical form are distinguished from meaningless ones that go beyond it, such those in ethics, aesthetics, and metaphysics.


Sense and Nonsense in the Tractatus: 

Wittgenstein distinguished rather clearly between what is "nonsense" and "sense" in language. His goal was to expose absurdity by making language more understandable and critical.


The Ladder Metaphor: 

Someone compared the Tractatus to a ladder. It was a tool for comprehension, but once its function was fulfilled, it was supposed to be thrown away as gibberish.


Later Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Wittgenstein's philosophical development progressed from the inflexible "Tractatus" to a more flexible viewpoint in his later work, the "Philosophical Investigations." This stage questioned several of his previous beliefs and placed an emphasis on the useful application of language:


Transition: 

The Tractatus's dogmatism was significantly broken by the later Wittgenstein. He moved the emphasis from the rigorous logic of the previous work to language use in daily life.


Meaning as Use: 

In the "Philosophical Investigations," Wittgenstein made the well-known claim that "meaning is use," contending that a word's meaning is established by its use in linguistic games and situations.


Language-Games and Family Resemblance: 

Wittgenstein developed the idea of "language-games" to highlight the variety of language use. He also talked about "family resemblance," which suggests that words become meaningful when they are used in different language games.



Philosophy as Therapy: 

According to Wittgenstein, philosophy is therapeutic. Its purpose was to point out and refute misconceptions about language, truth, thought, and philosophy that are present in conventional wisdom.


Anti-Dogmatism: 

He espoused a more flexible view of language and philosophy and criticized dogmatism.


Rule-Following and Private Language: 

Wittgenstein examined the idea of adhering to rules and the paradoxes that result from considering the acquisition and application of rules. Additionally, he offered the "private language argument," which stressed the necessity for meaningful language to adhere to public norms and standards.



Grammar and Form of Life: 

In his later writings, Wittgenstein emphasized the idea of "grammar," which encompasses the fundamentals of language as an activity guided by rules. He also presented the concept of "forms of life," emphasizing how language use is influenced by interpretation and environment.


Expanding Language's Horizons

Even though Wittgenstein's writings highlighted language's limitations, it's important to remember that language is still a potent tool for understanding, communicating, and researching the human condition. Thoughts and experiences can be communicated through language, yet it is unable to adequately capture the complexity of the world.


Beyond Words: The Power of Multilingualism

Multilingualism as an Expansive Tool


Wittgenstein's investigation into the limits of language prompts us to think about how multilingualism might extend perspectives and promote improved understanding and communication. Acquiring knowledge of several languages reveals the subsequent insights:


Language as a Tool: 

Language is an essential tool for interacting with others, expressing ideas, and transmitting information.


Language as a Constraint: 

Despite its intrinsic power, language is limited because it is unable to adequately convey the complexity of human experience.


Varieties of Communication: 

Body language, emotional expression, and nonverbal clues are all parts of communication that go beyond words.


Language Evolution: 

Over time, languages change to reflect shifts in society and subtle cultural differences.


Words and Concepts: 

The notions and ideas that people are able to express are directly influenced by the words used in their language.


Language as a Cultural Identifier: 

Language shapes people's perceptions of the world and interactions with others, and it is fundamental to culture and identity.


Bridging Language Barriers:

Multilingualism serves as a bridge to foster tolerance and understanding in an increasingly interconnected society.


Beyond Words: 

Certain facets of the human experience are too intimate and private to be expressed in words.


Conclusion: Embracing the Boundaries and Potential of Language

Wittgenstein's observations serve as a helpful reminder that, despite its limitations, language is nevertheless a vital instrument. It encapsulates the core of interpersonal communication, promoting understanding and bridging cultural divides. We may unleash the potential of multilingualism to broaden our horizons and strengthen our sense of community on a global scale by embracing the limits and possibilities of language.


Comprehending the Philosophy and Language Theory of Wittgenstein


Renowned philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein is well-known for his contributions to the philosophy of language. The following succinctly describes his philosophy:


Wittgenstein's Philosophy:


Two Major Works: 


Wittgenstein's philosophical career can be divided into two main periods: the early phase, which is typified by the "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus," and the later phase, which is mostly represented by "Philosophical Investigations."


Early Wittgenstein (Tractatus): 


Early on in his career, Wittgenstein put forth the notion of a "picture theory of language." According to him, ideas, words, and propositions are like images that depict real-world facts. During this era, his thinking was centered on the notion that logical structure and meaningful language coincide, and he attempted to define the boundaries of what was possible.



Later Wittgenstein (Philosophical Investigations): 


Wittgenstein moved away from the earlier dogmatism in his later philosophical writings. He underlined how crucial language is as a social activity that is guided by rules. Here, he proposed the idea that "meaning is use," implying that a word's meaning is established by its usage in different language games.


Wittgenstein on Language:


Early Wittgenstein: 


In his "Tractatus," Wittgenstein made the case that both cognition and language are world representations. He popularized the notion that meaningful ideas follow the logical structure of reality, and that language should reflect this structure. He held that language should only be used to express empirical truths; anything else, including metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics, should be dismissed as absurd.


Later Wittgenstein: 


In "Philosophical Investigations," Wittgenstein turned his attention to language's actual, daily applications. He popularized the idea of "language-games," which are a variety of language-based social activities with set rules and objectives. He maintained that words acquire meaning through their use in these language-games and that meaning is obtained from them.


"Meaning is Use": 


Wittgenstein is credited with saying, "meaning is use," which highlights the idea that a word's meaning is decided by its use in particular language games and settings. The conventional understanding of meaning as something connected to mental images or outside reality was contested by this point of view.


Private Language Argument:


Wittgenstein also opposed the idea of a "private language," arguing that language had to be available to the general public and adhere to accepted standards of accuracy in order to have meaning. He thought that language could not be limited to describing one's own, subjective experiences.


All things considered, Wittgenstein's philosophy changed throughout time, moving from an early emphasis on language as representation to a later emphasis on language as a practical and social activity, where meaning is obtained by language use in games and daily interactions. His work had a significant impact on the philosophy of language and continues to have ramifications in linguistics and philosophy.


Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus


Intellectual Roots:



developed from Wittgenstein's earlier writings and was affected by many concepts and Schopenhauer.



Reaction to Russell and Frege:



Reaction and continuation to the logic and language theories of Russell and Frege.



Seven Basic Propositions:


The basis for the investigation of philosophy, logic, and language throughout the book.


Representation of the World: 


Thinking represents the world, therefore propositions and thinking have the same logical structure.


Complexity of States of Affairs:



The world is made up of both potential and existing situations.



The Picture Theory:



Ideas and statements are representations that line up with the situation's logical framework.



The Limits of Language:

Logical form, reference, and linguistic limitations are followed by meaningful statements; ethics, aesthetics, and metaphysics are not included.


Sense and Nonsense in the Tractatus

Limits of Language:



Distinguishes sense from nonsense in language, focusing on representation.



Two Kinds of Nonsense:



Identifies senseless and nonsensical propositions.



Use of Language Beyond the Bounds:



Philosopher's role is to clarify and critique language, exposing nonsense.



Saying vs. Showing:



Differentiates between expressing in language and demonstrating through other means.



Metaphysical and Ethical Limitations:



Excludes traditional metaphysics, ethics, aesthetics, and solipsism from meaningful discourse.



The Ladder Metaphor:



Describes the purpose of the Tractatus as a tool for understanding and then discarding as nonsense.



The Later Wittgenstein and Philosophical

InvestigationsTransition:



Shifts from the dogmatism of the Tractatus to focusing on language as use.



Meaning as Use:



Meaning of a word is its use in language, challenging the traditional view of meaning as representation.



Language-Games and Family Resemblance:



Introduces language-games and family resemblance to emphasize diverse language use.


Philosophy as Therapy:



Views philosophy as therapeutic, exposing and critiquing fallacies in traditional thinking about language, truth, thought, and philosophy.



Anti-Dogmatism:



Rejects dogmatism for a more fluid perspective on language and philosophy.



Rule-Following and Private Language Rule-Following:



Wittgenstein explores how rules are learned and followed, challenging mentalistic and Platonistic assumptions.



Skeptical Paradox:



Proposition 201 presents a paradox, questioning the determination of rule-following.



Private-Language Argument:



Emphasizes that meaningful language must be subject to public standards and criteria.



Grammar and Form of Life Wittgenstein's Grammar:



Grammar encompasses the essence of language as a rule-governed activity, different from his earlier strict logic in the Tractatus.



Forms of Life:



Forms of life serve as a background to language and shared human behavior, depending on context and interpretation.



Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein



Publication and Translations: 


German version first published in 1921; English translation by C.K. Ogden and F. P. Ramsey published in 1922. Later on, D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness retranslated it.


Intellectual Roots:


originated from Wittgenstein's earlier writings, which included "Notes on Logic," "Notes Dictated to G. E. Moore," and his Notebooks. Schopenhauer and other cultural concepts had an influence on these works.


Reaction to Russell and Frege:


Reflects a response to and a continuation of the ideas about language and logic put forward by Russell and Frege. Wittgenstein corresponded extensively with Keynes, Russell, and Moore.


Seven Basic Propositions:


The structure of the book is based on seven fundamental ideas that provide the basis for its investigation of language, logic, and philosophy.


Representation of the World:



According to Wittgenstein's philosophy, propositions and thought have the same logical structure, which means that they are both representations of facts.


Complexity of States of Affairs:


States of affairs are intricate arrangements of distinct internal characteristics that define their logical shape. There are real and potential states of affairs in the globe.


The Picture Theory:



The idea put forth by Wittgenstein that ideas and propositions are like images, and that the logical structure of these pictures matches the logical structure of the situation they represent.


The Limits of Language:


Wittgenstein comes to the conclusion that only statements that follow the rules of language, have a reference, and have logical form can be considered meaningful. This limits the scope of philosophy to exclude metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics.


Sense and Nonsense in the Tractatus



Limits of Language: 


Wittgenstein's Tractatus aims to draw limits for language, distinguishing between sense and nonsense, with a focus on representation.



Two Kinds of Nonsense:



Wittgenstein distinguishes between senseless propositions (e.g., tautologies and contradictions) and nonsensical propositions that transcend the bounds of sense.


Use of Language Beyond the Bounds:



The philosopher's role is to clarify and critique language, particularly pointing out where it goes wrong, showing that some propositions are nonsense.


Saying vs. Showing:


Wittgenstein differentiates between saying (expressing in language) and showing (demonstrating through means other than language) as a way to address ineffable truths.



Metaphysical and Ethical Limitations:


Wittgenstein's critique extends to traditional metaphysics, ethics, aesthetics, and solipsism, excluding them from meaningful discourse.



The Ladder Metaphor:


Wittgenstein uses the ladder metaphor to describe the purpose of the Tractatus: to be used for understanding and then discarded as nonsense.



The Later Wittgenstein and Philosophical


Investigations


Transition from Tractatus to Philosophical Investigations:


Wittgenstein's later philosophy marks a departure from the dogmatism of his earlier work, focusing on language as use.


Meaning as Use:


Wittgenstein proposes that the meaning of a word is its use in language, challenging the traditional view of meaning as representation.



Language-Games and Family Resemblance:


Wittgenstein introduces the concept of language-games to emphasize the diversity of language use. He rejects general explanations and suggests family resemblance as a better way to connect the uses of a concept.



Philosophy as Therapy:


Wittgenstein's later philosophy views philosophy as a therapeutic activity, aiming to expose and critique fallacies in traditional ways of thinking about language, truth, thought, and philosophy.



Anti-Dogmatism:


Wittgenstein's later work rejects dogmatism and promotes a more fluid and open perspective on language and philosophy, focusing on the context of language use in everyday life.


Wittgenstein on Rule-Following and Private Language


In Ludwig Wittgenstein's later philosophy, rule-following plays a central role in exploring the issue of word usage universality. According to Wittgenstein, rules are abstract concepts that are not limited to any particular use. This article analyzes related topics and provides examples to illustrate Wittgenstein's theory of rule-following. It discusses important interpretations and objections to his theories, particularly Proposition 201's skeptical dilemma. The ultimate goal of Wittgenstein's writings is to free us from mentalistic and platonistic presumptions. The private-language argument is also covered in the essay, with a focus on the necessity of public standards for meaningful language.


One of the philosophical questions that is most strongly linked to Ludwig Wittgenstein's later works is the subject of rule-following. This topic, which sprang from previous concerns, becomes a focal point of discussion in the context of what can be stated to be universally applicable to the different uses of a term. The idea that a rule is an abstract entity that transcends its specific implementations is at the core of this discussion. Gaining an understanding of a rule is grasping this abstract concept and learning how to apply it.



In the opening example of his investigation, Wittgenstein states that "... we instruct a pupil to continue a series (e.g., 'add 2') beyond 1000, and the pupil writes 1000, 1004, 1008, 1012" (PI 185). The student's reaction poses significant queries when they are corrected and asked why they persisted in the same way. Wittgenstein goes on to methodically dissect a group of connected questions, mostly in sections 185–243 of the Philosophical Investigations, though his findings are also found elsewhere: How are rules taught to us? How do we adhere to them? What standards are used to evaluate if a rule has been correctly followed? Do these standards exist in the mind, maybe in conjunction with a mental image of the rule? When applying rules, do we rely on intuition?  Or are social and public procedures used to teach and enforce rules? The responses are not given in an affirmative, in a very Wittgensteinian fashion; instead, the question frames itself as having a logical content that is questioned. Wittgenstein is committed to freeing us from mentalistic and platonistic presumptions. This freedom means that there is no longer any need to posit any authority, internal or external, other from the practical uses of a rule.



Our discussion culminates in Proposition 201, which is widely regarded as the issue's turning point: "This was our conundrum: no course of action could be dictated by a rule, since every course of action could be shown to comply with the rule." The response was that everything might be interpreted to either support or contradict the rule if it could be made out to do so. Thus, there would be no agreement or disagreement in this situation." This dilemma, which is almost a contradiction now that it has been formulated by Wittgenstein, has generated a great deal of discussion and interpretation. Everyone agrees that this statement captures the essence of the general issue of meaning, comprehension, and language use. According to a well-known reading of the rule-following paradox, Wittgenstein expressed a skeptical conundrum and offered a congruent skeptical solution. This view was first put forth by Fogelin in 1976 and then refined by Kripke in 1982. This point of view holds that there are no objective facts that can conclusively define what constitutes abiding by a rule. Wittgenstein responds by offering substitute circumstances that could support our claim that an individual is really abiding by the law. Nonetheless, this view has encountered opposition from a number of alternative perspectives, such as those put forth by McGinn in 1984, Baker and Hacker in 1984, and Cavell in 1990. Additionally, a number of academics have contributed some new insights, including Diamond in "Rules: Looking in the Right Place," which was published in Phillips and Winch in 1989, and multiple articles in Miller and Wright in 2002.


The portions of the Philosophical Investigations that interpreters often refer to as "the private-language argument" come after the rule-following parts, and might therefore be viewed as the conclusion of the discussion. These parts illustrate a basic idea, though Wittgenstein never called it an argument: in order for a speech to have meaning, it should, in theory, be subject to public standards and correctness requirements. So, a private language is not a true, meaningful, rule-governed language when "words... are meant to refer to what only the speaker can know—specifically, to the speaker's immediate private sensations..." (PI 243). Language signs can only serve their intended purpose when it is possible to judge whether or not they are being used correctly; as Wittgenstein states, "the use of [a] word stands in need of a justification which everybody understands" (PI 261).


Wittgenstein's Grammar and the Form of Life


According to Wittgenstein, grammar has a more expansive and enigmatic function. Unlike the rigorous logic of his previous Tractatus, it captures the essence of language as a distinct, rule-governed activity. This section examines Wittgenstein's theory that grammar is context-dependent and interwoven into common language games. We talk about Wittgenstein's idea of "forms of life" as the foundation for language and common human behavior. The subtle interpretations of life forms, which range from relativistic to more universalist viewpoints, are also discussed in this piece.


In Wittgenstein's philosophy, grammar—which is typically viewed as a system of rules guiding the proper syntactic and semantic usage of language—takes on a more expansive and enigmatic meaning. Under his direction, grammar develops into an idea that encapsulates language as a special kind of rule-governed activity. This idea takes the place of the stricter, purist logic that was essential to Wittgenstein's earlier Tractatus, where it provided the framework for language and the universe. According to Wittgenstein, "Grammar expresses essence; it tells us what kind of object anything is." (Theology as grammar)" (PI 371–373). In Wittgenstein's framework, grammar "rules" are not clear, technical directions to be followed irrespective of context, unlike the prescriptive rules found in grammar books. Rather, they are called upon only in certain situations, chiefly when philosophical confusion misleads us into false language illusions. Wittgenstein notes, "I can know what someone else is thinking, but not what I am thinking." as an example. Saying "I know what you are thinking" is appropriate, but saying "I know what I am thinking" is incorrect. (A drop of grammar containing a huge cloud of philosophy)" (Page 222 of Philosophical Investigations, 1953). In this instance, understanding the linguistic quirks of first-person avowals protects us against the dangers inherent in basic epistemology.


According to Wittgenstein's philosophy, grammar is an integral part of ordinary language games and exists within them. "The word 'language-game' is used here to emphasize the fact that speaking is part of an activity, or a way of life," according to Wittgenstein (PI 23). The different forms of life are what make language possible and, as a result, are taken for granted. "It is not only agreement in definitions but also (odd as it may sound) in judgments that is required," according to Wittgenstein (PI 242). This agreement centers on the common form of life rather than on beliefs that are held in common (PI 241). Perhaps unexpectedly, there are only five instances of the idea of forms of life in Wittgenstein's Investigations. However, it has created a great deal of interpretive difficulties, resulting in a variety of even contradictory readings. It is possible to think of life forms as constantly evolving and context-dependent, influenced by a variety of elements such as culture and history. On the other hand, they may be viewed as a shared human history or "shared human behavior," acting as a frame of reference for understanding a foreign language (PI 206). The concept of forms of life is interpreted differently depending on the context. It can be interpreted as relativistic in certain cases or as expressing a deeper human foundation for language and culture in others.


Some important and representative propositions from the book are these:



1 The world is all that is the case.
4.01 A proposition is a picture of reality.
4.0312 …My fundamental idea is that the ‘logical constants’ are not representatives; that there can be no representatives of the logic of facts.
4.121 …Propositions show the logical form of reality. They display it.
4.1212 What can be shown, cannot be said.
4.5 …The general form of a proposition is: This is how things stand.
5.43 …all the propositions of logic say the same thing, to wit nothing.
5.4711 To give the essence of a proposition means to give the essence of all description, and thus the essence of the world.
5.6 The limits of my language mean the limits of my world.



The world encompasses everything that exists.

When we make statements, they serve as visual representations of how things are.

The fundamental premise is that words such as "and," "or," and "not" do not represent things, therefore there are no representatives for how facts work.

Statements expose the structure of reality by demonstrating how things fit together.

What we can directly demonstrate with photos or examples cannot always be fully articulated in words.

Statements usually follow the same pattern: "This is how things are."

Every logical assertion conveys the same fundamental message: nothing.

Capturing the essence of a statement entails capturing the essence of all descriptions and, as a result, the essence of the world.

The bounds of our language dictate the limits of our understanding of the world.



Wittgenstein's "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus" has seven major assertions that embody his distinct philosophical approach. Let us examine these issues seriously and consider their far-reaching repercussions.

"The world is all that is the case." Wittgenstein's introductory statement reflects a lifelong commitment to empirical inquiry. It parallels a central tenet of logical positivism, emphasizing the need of scientific data in comprehending the universe. However, it raises the question of whether there are components of reality that are not empirically verifiable.


"A proposition is a picture of reality." Wittgenstein's analogy of propositions to pictures suggests that language is fundamentally representational. While this provides a vivid understanding of how language interacts with the environment, it raises the question of whether language can effectively reflect the complexities and subtleties of reality.


"My fundamental idea is that the 'logical constants' are not representatives; that there can be no representatives of the logic of facts." Wittgenstein questions standard conceptions of representation, highlighting that logical constants (such as "and," "or," and "not") do not represent anything in the real world. This hypothesis raises fascinating concerns regarding the nature of abstract conceptions and the organization of logical reasoning.


"Propositions demonstrate the logical structure of reality." They put it on display." Wittgenstein's emphasis on propositions exposing the logical structure of reality emphasizes the importance of language as a tool for discovering the world's order and organization. However, it raises concerns regarding the link between language and reality. Propositions either reflect structure or actively change our understanding of it.


"What can be shown, cannot be said." This puzzling notion highlights language's limitations in fully representing reality. It implies that there are dimensions of experience and comprehension that are beyond the scope of language. This forces us to evaluate the limits of linguistic expression as well as the role of nonverbal modes of communication.


"The general form of a proposition is: This is how things stand." Wittgenstein's concise formulation stresses propositions' declarative nature, portraying them as statements about the state of circumstances. It invites us to consider the act of producing statements and how it impacts our worldview.


"The limits of my language mean the limits of my world." Wittgenstein's final statement emphasizes the fundamental relationship between language and our understanding of reality. It is similar to the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis in that it proposes that the structure of our language may define the bounds of our cognitive environment. It invites us to consider how language simultaneously supports and constrains our understanding.

The Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus of Ludwig Wittgenstein encourages us to reconsider the relationship between language and reality, the role of logical constants, and the bounds of our cognitive universe. It invites us to consider the limits of verbal expression as well as the breadth of what may be communicated about the world. Wittgenstein's findings continue to pique our interest in philosophy and encourage us to investigate the complicated interplay between language and our perception of the cosmos.

He says in proposition 4.003 that:



Most of the propositions and questions of philosophers arise from our failure to understand the logic of our language. (They belong to the same class as the question whether the good is more or less identical than the beautiful.) And it is not surprising that the deepest problems are in fact not problems at all.




In Philosophical Investigations Sect. 90 Wittgenstein says:


Our investigation is a grammatical one. Such an investigation sheds light on our problem by clearing misunderstandings away. Misunderstandings concerning the use of words, caused, among other things, by certain analogies between the forms of expression in different regions of language.



In 1931 Wittgenstein described his task thus:


Language sets everyone the same traps; it is an immense network of easily accessible wrong turnings. And so we watch one man after another walking down the same paths and we know in advance where he will branch off, where walk straight on without noticing the side turning, etc. etc. What I have to do then is erect signposts at all the junctions where there are wrong turnings so as to help people past the danger points.


Meaning:

According to Section 43 of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, "for a substantial class of cases-though not for all-in which we apply the word "meaning," it can be defined thus: "the meaning of a word is its use in the language."



Wittgenstein's perspective on word meaning, as described in Philosophical Investigations Sect. 43, says that word meaning is essentially decided by how a word is employed in language.


Wittgenstein's position opposes the notions that meaning is related to identifying objects or is dependent on subjective psychological sensations, emphasizing the importance of a word's use in determining its meaning.


Understanding the meaning of a word entails understanding its reference, slang status, part of speech, and connotations, all of which contribute to its meaning.


In contrast to scientific inquiries into areas such as awareness, Wittgenstein's philosophy advocates tackling philosophical concerns by analyzing the various uses of language.


Wittgenstein's "meaning is use" premise is broken down in Philosophical Investigations Sect. 561, where he addresses the word "is" having two distinct uses and meanings (as a copula and a symbol of equality).


Wittgenstein emphasizes the non-arbitrary nature of conceptual distinctions, arguing that whether a notion is accidental or fundamental depends on how it is employed in our language and lives.


Wittgenstein emphasizes the importance of "forms of life" and the influence of one's environment, needs, emotions, and sensory capacities in developing one's understanding, making empathy and mutual understanding difficult when there are significant differences.



Rules and Private Language:


Wittgenstein's point of view emphasizes the importance of common attitudes, relevance, and consistent answers in facilitating effective communication.


Color agreement is a fundamental component of language, being part of our perception of color, and regularity of usage is an essential aspect of language, not a logical necessity.


The relationship between language and way of life begs the question of whether a lonely individual can have their own language, which remains an open question.


The discussion over lonely individuals and their ability to follow rules, including linguistic ones, calls into question the concept of a "private language," which Wittgenstein investigates in another context.


Wittgenstein's critique of "private language" demonstrates the incoherence of certain beliefs about language and private experiences, demonstrating their limitations.


Wittgenstein's philosophy does not qualify him as a behaviorist; he recognizes the existence of sensations and experiences but discourages them from being interpreted as private things referred to by public language.


While influenced by Wittgenstein, Saul A. Kripke's theory on rule-following and language interpretation remains a topic of interpretation and controversy, as Wittgenstein was cautious to support philosophical theories. The clue may be found in Wittgenstein's distinction between grasping and understanding rules.


In his acclaimed book Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (1982), Saul Kripke presents a fresh interpretation of Ludwig Wittgenstein's principal observations in his later works, particularly Philosophical Investigations (1953) and, to a lesser extent, observations on the Foundations of Mathematics (1956).


According to Kripke's causal theory of reference, the referent of a given use of a proper name, such as Aristotle, is transmitted through an indefinitely long series of earlier uses; this series constitutes a causal-historical chain that, in theory, can be traced back to an original, or "baptismal," use. 


There is no fact about a speaker's behavioral, mental, or social life that can metaphysically determine, or constitute, what she means by her words and also fix a determinate connection between those meanings and the correctness of her use of these words, according to the skeptical argument that Kripke extracts from Wittgenstein's later remarks on meaning and rule-following. Such a skeptical conclusion has devastating consequences for the classical realist conception of meaning: if we persist on the idea that meaning is primarily a factual affair, we arrive at the odd conclusion that "no such thing as meaning anything by any word" exists (Kripke 1982, 55).





Ray Monk: "Wittgenstein in Cambridge"


Bertrand Russell on Ludwig Wittgenstein

Wittgenstein's Tractatus


Great Minds - Part 5 - The Latter Wittgenstein: The Philosophy of Language

Tags

Post a Comment

0 Comments
* Please Don't Spam Here. All the Comments are Reviewed by Admin.